Reflecting on political violence, Žižek distinguishes between a violence of action, which testifies above all to the agent’s impotence, a violence which aims to preserve what is, to guarantee that nothing changes (e.g. Fascism), and lastly, the violence which changes the points of reference of a reality. “In order for this last kind of violence to take place, the very place should be opened up through a gesture which is thoroughly violent in its impassive refusal, through a gesture of pure withdrawal in which … nothing will have taken place but the place itself.” (381)

Why Is Bartleby Charging Method

Bartleby, for Žižek, exemplifies such a gesture. “I would prefer not to” is not equivalent to “I don’t prefer (or care) to.” To his employer’s orders, he does not refuse them specifically, but rather states a preference not to do them. For Žižek, this is a passage from a politics of “resistance” or “protestation”, which is defined inevitably in relation to what it rejects, “to a politics which opens up a new space outside the hegemonic position and its negation.” (381-2)
This is not Hardt’s and Negri’s reading of Bartleby, where his preference not to is seen as but a first moment in rejecting existing socio-political order, to be followed by a second moment which is that of constituting a new community, in the absence of which the protest ends in futility. According to Žižek, Bartleby’s refusal is not the start of anything, something to be subsequently overcome, but rather the primordial and ever present moment that underlies political construction. And therefore Bartleby does not simply say no to established order, a resistance which the system can always use to reproduce itself through the resistance’s participation in it, even if only negatively. Bartleby walks away from the system altogether.
But how can this separation be given body, without destroying it, or at least threatening to do so? Žižek’s concept of the parallax, as the essence of the dialectic, remains in this instance a metaphor; a metaphor that cannot keep at bay sovereignty’s revulsion for withdrawal.
Jacques Rancière
For Ranciere, the tension here amounts to a contradiction, an insurmountable contradiction.
[H]ow can one make a difference [establish order] in a political community with this indifference [Bartleby’s]? Difference must be made by an intercessor, by the Christ-like figure of the one who returns, “eyes turned red”, from the other side, from the place of justice, from the desert, and has nothing to say except indifference. This intercessor must then perform not one but two operations. He must oppose the old law of the fathers with the great anarchy of being, the justice of the desert. But he must also convert this justice into another, make this anarchy the principle of a world of justice conceived on the Platonic model: a world where human multiplicities are ordered according to their deserts.
Bartleby is … the new Christ or the brother to us all.

Gilles Deleuze, Essays Critical and clinical

What is then to be made of Bartleby’s politics of desire, or politics beyond sovereignty? Deleuze’s Bartleby is read from what he calls Bartleby’s formula: “I would prefer not to.” The statement’s termination, “not to”, “leaves what it reject undetermined”, bestowing upon the phrase then a kind of “limit function”. (68) It neither affirms nor negates, neither refuses nor accepts; the formula suspends both possibilities, and thus Bartleby withdraws from action. “The formula is devastating because it eliminates the preferable just as mercilessly as the nonpreferred. It not only abolishes the term it refers to, and that it rejects, but also abolishes the other term that it seemed to preserve, and that becomes impossible. In fact, it renders them indistinct. … All particularity, all reference is abolished.” (71) Bartleby expresses not a nihilistic will to nothingness, but rather a growing nothingness of the will. He is urged to say yes or no to what is demanded of him, but either response would translate into his defeat. His survival, his strength, is born of his withdrawal from all affirmation or negation; his pure passivity, his being “as being, and nothing more.” (71) “If Bartleby had refused, he could still be seen as a rebel or insurrectionary, and as such would still have a social role. But the formula stymies all speech acts, and at the same time, it makes Bartleby a pure outsider to whom no social position can be attributed.” (73)
All of which condemns the attorney’s efforts to understand and to help Bartleby to failure, for the attorney can only grasp another from within a general, hierarchical distribution of social functions. Bartleby’s radicalism is that he appears and prefers to be outside all such functionality. Before it, he places preference, the preference not to prefer, or desire, the desire not to desire. “Bartleby is the man without references, without possessions, without properties, without qualities, without particularities: he is too smooth for anyone to be able to hang any particularity on him. Without past or future, he is instantaneous.” (74) For Deleuze, Bartleby is one example among many to be found in 19th century literature of a search for a new man, a man without a name, and as nameless, a regicide or parricide. (74) Such figures reveal the artificiality, emptiness and mediocrity of our world and its orders. They reveal the possibility of a world beyond the father, the law, “a society of brothers as a new universality.” (84) Deleuze’s brothers and sisters are not filial; they are not rooted in consanguinity. They rather share in the nature of Agamben’s friendship. They are tied by an “alliance”, a “blood pact”, “drawing its members into an unlimited becoming.” (84) “A brother, a sister, all the more true for no longer being “his” or “hers”, since all “property”, all “proprietorship”, has disappeared. A burning passion deeper than love, since it no longer has either substance or qualities, but traces a zone of indiscernibility in which it passes through all intensities in every direction …”. (84)
Change outlook 365 email password. If both conditions are true,it is highly recommended that you use the Outlook keeps asking for my password diagnostic to troubleshoot issues in which Outlook continually prompts for a password. This diagnostic does automated checks and returns possible solutions for you to use to try to fix any detected issues. You will get the activation prompt and then If account is already added you will see the password prompt for app and ADAL again. Please do 2-Factor Authentication if asked to. If that doesn't work, do steps 2-4 but restart the Mac before launching Outlook.
A community, a political community of friends; of men and women without qualities or property, held together by nothing more than confidence in each other and in their ability to become, together, in this world.
Rpg maker vx materia system 2. The greatest objection to the principle of sovereignty has never been so well incarnated than by the copyist Bartleby.

Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer: le pouvoir souverain et la vie nue

Sovereignty is rooted in the power to establish the exception, the ban, as Carl Schmitt so powerfully stated it. It is however a paradoxical power, establishing as it does a legal-political order while itself outside that same order. It is a limit concept, and this necessarily, for the constituted regime is defined against and with what it excludes; and this not as some past, original act, but permanently.
For Agamben, sovereignty, in continuity with and beyond Schmitt, is the mechanism through which life (zoe), common to all living beings, is rendered properly human life, a life given form (bios, and thus, for e.g., bios politikos). Sovereignty is accordingly a metaphysical act.
The movement of sovereignty can be traced back to the relation of potentiality and actuality: the sovereign actualises potential life. The relation between the two however is no simpler than that between the constituting and constituted powers of sovereignty. But it is here, through the work of Aristotle, that Agamben will try to trace a path beyond the violence of sovereignty, by trying to grasp the existence and autonomy of potentiality.
For Aristotle, potentiality precedes actuality and determines it. Yet it also appears to be subordinate to actuality, in that potentiality only exists in the act. Aristotle however does insist on the autonomous existence of potentiality (the artist, for example, perceives her/his potential as creator in the absence of creating). But for potentiality to possess its own reality, it is necessary that it may also not act, that it be in itself the power to not be or do. (HS:54) “Every potentiality is at one and the same time a potentiality for the opposite … .That, then, which is capable of being, may either be or not be; the same thing, then, is capable both of being and of not being”. (Met. 1050b10) The potential to be is in other words precisely the potential that may not act, not realise itself. It maintains itself in relation to its actuality in the form of its suppression: its sovereignty is its impotence. (HS:55)
If it is recalled that in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, the examples of the potential to not be are always taken from the domain of human arts and knowledge, it can be said that man is the living being who exists immanently in the dimension of potentiality, the potentiality or power of not to be, that is, contingency. All human potential is equally impotence. (PP:240)
Why Is Bartleby Charging Me
How then is the passage from potentiality to actuality possible? How is it to be thought? Aristotle’s answer is the following: “A thing is potentially some thing or act when, in the passage to actuality of which it is the potentiality, nothing will be which cannot be.” (Met. 1047a24-6) This is not to affirm that all is possible which is not impossible (a mere tautology), but rather points to the condition of the realisation of a potentiality. The potential, the possible, cannot pass into an act without positing its power to not be, its powerlessness, its impotence. The powerlessness affirmed does not signify the destruction of its actuality, but rather, its realisation, the way in which power, what is potential, turns towards itself to give itself to itself, without end. (HS: 55-6; De Anima 417b2-7) In other words, potentiality is that which always exceeds its forms and realisations; it is a power to become, permanently. (As Aristotle says of thought, in De Anima: “When thought has become each thing in the way in which a man who actually knows is said to do so …, its condition is still one of potentiality, but in a different sense from the potentiality which preceded the acquisition of knowledge by learning or discovery; and thought is then able to think of itself.” 429b5-9).
Returning then to the paradox of sovereignty, for Agamben, the difficulty of thinking through potentiality and the need to grasp its autonomy is essential to the rethinking of sovereignty. Aristotle’s philosophy offers a paradigm for sovereignty, one in which the sovereign act is that which is realised simply by suppressing its own potential to not be. But the suppression cannot in fact be effective, for otherwise sovereignty would destroy itself. The sovereign acts continuously to secure the exception and is thus perpetually at the limit of its own reality. To move beyond the violence of the exception, it is necessary to think the existence of potentiality, power, without any relation to actuality, to no longer think the act as the accomplishment and manifestation of potentiality. (HS:57) The figure of Bartleby is precisely an experiment in such thinking, according to Agamben. Bartleby is an example of perfect potentiality, which nothing separates from the act of creation. “Bartleby is the extreme figure of the Nothing from which all creation derives; and at the same time, he constitutes the most implacable vindication of this Nothing as pure, absolute potentiality.” (P: 253-4) Morality and politics has typically sought to submit potentiality to will and necessity. (P:254) It is what Bartleby’s employer attempts to do, with singular failure. And the belief that potentiality can be so restrained is the “perpetual illusion of morality” and the violence of sovereignty. (P:254)
Bartleby puts into question the supremacy of will over potentiality. (P:254) But he thereby does not do nothing. Instead, Bartleby’s doing exceeds his will. “It is not that he does not want to copy or that he does not want to leave the office; he simply would prefer not to.” (P:255) Bartleby’s formula destroys any possible relation between being able and willing, “between potentia absoluta and potentia ordinate.” (P:255)
Bartleby is pure possibility, freed from any connection to a reason, or subordination to reality. (P:258) He unravels exigencies, disarms imperatives and opens up a life beyond moral command and sovereign law. He creates nothing, but makes all creation possible, a creation never exhausted; what Agamben calls a decreation.

Why Is Bartleby Charging Me On Facebook

Bartleby’s politics is not a politics of truth or goodness. It is rather a politics of the gesture, of a form of life; a life lived as such, in friendship and in openness; a politics of pure possibility.
Works referred to, in the order cited:
Maurice Blanchot, The Writing of the Disaster, University of Nebraska Press, 1995.
Georges Bataille, “L’experiénce intérieure” and “Méthode de méditation”, in Œuvres Complètes V, Gallimard, 1973.
Herman Melville, Bartleby and Benito Cereno, Dover Publications, 1990.
Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Empire, Harvard University Press, 2000.
Tiqqun, Tout a failli, vive le communisme!, La Fabrique, 2009.
Giorgio Agamben, L’amitié, Éditions Payot et Rivages, 2007.
Slavoj Žižek, The Parallax View, The MIT Press, 2006.
Jacques Rancière, “Deleuze, Bartleby and the Literary Formula”, in The Flesh of Words. The Politics of Writing, Stanford University Press, 2004.
Gilles Deleuze, “Bartleby, or The Formula”, in Essays Critical and Clinical, Verso, 1998.
Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer: le pouvoir souverain et la vie nue, Éditions du Seuil, 1997.
Aristotle, “Metaphysics”, in The Complete Works of Aristotle: Vol. Two, Princeton University Press, 1984.
Giorgio Agamben, “La puissance de la pensée”, La puissance de la pensée : essais et conférences, Éditions Payot et Rivages, 2006
Aristotle, “de Anima”, in The Complete Works of Aristotle: Vol. One, Princeton University Press, 1984.
Giorgio Agamben, “Bartleby, or On Contingency”, in Potentialities, Stanford University Press, 1999.
How an 1853 short story gave today's movement against the 1 percent a tag-line and a heroic example of how to possess political space.
On May 1, students and activists are planning to revive the Occupy Wall Street movement with a general strike. One poster making the rounds on Facebook and other social media features a hamster nervously eyeing a treadmill, and above it the famous words, 'I WOULD PREFER NOT TO.' The hamster's wheel of course represents the drudgery of our modern routines; the phrase, many will recall, comes from Herman Melville's 1853 story 'Bartleby, the Scrivener.' Subtitled 'A Tale of Wall Street,' this cryptic narrative traces the sad fate of a passive-aggressive writer who refuses to vacate the offices of a corporate lawyer. Bartleby was the first laid-off worker to occupy Wall Street.
It may seem odd to understand Occupy Wall Street through a story written 150 years before the tents went up in Zuccotti Park, when no one had heard of a human microphone and when Trinity Church was the tallest building in New York. But Bartleby literally does occupy Wall Street -- specifically the offices of Melville's narrator, a lawyer for the 19th century one-percenters who does 'a snug business among rich men's bonds and mortgages and title-deeds.' And the way that Melville represents Bartleby's occupation can help us understand the power of the endlessly intriguing movement that is promising to return with renewed fervor this spring. What's more, this staple of the English Literature curriculum can speak to the ways that Wall Street itself is coming to occupy the classroom itself.

Recommended Reading

Recommended Reading

Why should this sad scrivener, of all people, be the symbol for a politically disruptive movement?
The word 'occupy' itself recurs with startling frequency throughout Melville's story to describe Bartleby's inactive action of staying put without working. At first the narrator is pleased with the steadiness of Bartleby's occupation of his office, since the scrivener works productively, but when the narrator stops by on a Sunday, he is unsettled to find that his own clerk (who is making his home there) refuses to admit him to the office: 'Not yet,' says Bartleby, 'I am occupied.' When Bartleby stops working, the lawyer wonders, like a weak-hearted Bloomberg, whether he should evict the stubborn copyist. He is gripped by a queasy vision in which the occupier of Wall Street becomes its possessor: 'The idea came upon me of his possibly turning out a long-lived man, and keep occupying my chambers, and denying my authority.' Bartleby, he fears, will eventually 'claim possession of [his] office by right of his perpetual occupancy.' Even after the scrivener is evicted from the office, Bartleby continues to cause 'great tribulation' by 'persisting in occupying the entry.'
When, the narrator wonders, does occupation become possession? Who has a right to occupy what space? Who must work for whom? What happens in our society to those who can't -- or simply won't -- work? What obligations do we have to those who prefer not to fit into the system, or run on the hamster's wheel? The narrator would like simple answers to such questions. He tries to view his conflict with Bartleby as a matter of property rights, and when he urges Bartleby to vacate, he sounds a lot like a wealthy suburban homeowner: 'What earthly right have you to stay here? Do you pay any rent? Do you pay my taxes? Or is this property yours?'
Yet against this language of property rights, the story introduces a subtle counter-discourse of hazy motives, wishes and feelings. Bartleby's 'queer word' of choice, to prefer, injects into the story a defiant note of desire, shifting our analysis of his occupancy from economic rights to preferences and wishes. (Bartleby appears never to touch the money that he is paid, removing himself from the money economy altogether.) As a wealthy but good-intentioned liberal, the narrator struggles to understand Bartleby's motives -- to determine, ultimately, the extent to which his ethical obligations to Bartleby exceed his legal ones.
Like many of Melville's stories, 'Bartleby' at once demands and frustrates interpretation. The unclarity of Bartleby's aims -- What does he actually want? What are his demands? -- invites our attention but defeats our reading. By refusing to articulate specific demands, Bartleby defies the very terms on which Wall Street does business. Melville thus provides a prescient illustration of the force of the Occupy movement. For although those of us who support Occupy tend to agree about matters such as anti-poverty programs, tax fairness, workers' rights, and the regulation of financial markets, OWS seemed last fall to gain political power precisely as it held back from articulating any specific list of policy demands -- holding back, in Bartleby-like fashion, from any self-definition that might diminish the unsettling force of the movement and allow it to be co-opted by politics as usual. The blank Bartlebyan inscrutability of Occupy Wall Street came to constitute its greatest power.
Yet why should this sad scrivener, of all people, be the symbol for a politically disruptive movement? Wouldn't a famous political radical make a better poster boy -- as the Tea Partiers of the American Revolution have done for their contemporary right-wing namesakes? Bartleby is among the first modern bureaucrats to serve as a literary hero. Working before the invention of the mimeograph, he copies legal documents with perfect accuracy. This is soul-killing work. 'To some sanguine temperaments,' muses Melville's narrator, 'it would be altogether intolerable.. I cannot credit that the mettlesome poet Byron would have contentedly sat down with Bartleby to examine a law document of, say five hundred pages, closely written in a crimpy hand.' The invocation of Byron is crucial; Bartleby's writing is as far from poetry as you can get. It is bureaucratic scrivening, in which there is no room for originality, authorship, style, ornament, or pleasure. Is it any wonder that Bartleby 'decide[s] upon doing no more writing'?

Why Is Bartleby Charging Means

The OWS poster that quotes Bartleby describes May 1st as a day of no work. It also, appropriately, calls it a day of no school. For Wall Street these days is increasingly encroaching upon the classroom. Hedge fund managers and for-profit operations are taking over public education. The logic of management consultants guides the so-called education reform movement, which shuts down and reopens schools like unprofitable retail outlets at a strip mall. As an English professor, I am increasingly kept busy by bureaucracy; my colleagues and I lament our inability to do our 'real writing' because we are always scrivening -- reading, writing, revising, signing, forwarding, developing, and implementing the proposals, initiatives, forms, memos, and documents that the system mandates. Under the indistinguishable education policies of George W. Bush and Barack Obama, today's teachers must, like Bartleby, reproduce without variation the curricula and lessons dictated from on high.

Why Is Bartleby Charging Me On Amazon

Yet perhaps because Wall Street's influence on education has become so great, we are starting to hear calls to occupy the classroom. More and more I see the phrase scrawled in colored chalk on the walkways of the university that employs me, Montclair State. The Occupy movement has targeted some public meetings of the New York City Department of Education. Against the putative reformers who see teachers and students as mere copyists, Herman Melville's enigmatic fable -- written when our modern capitalist bureaucracy was just emerging -- might help us think of today's students not as future scriveners but as future intellectuals who can question the conditions under which we all learn and live. Bartleby, the first worker to occupy Wall Street, can now help us to occupy the classroom. Imagine what would happen if, confronted by the mandates of Race to the Top, students, teachers, principals, and even governors would state, simply and plainly, 'I would prefer not to'?